In preparation for a lecture on mind and nature in German Idealism, I’m working my way through Kant’s third of three critiques, the Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790). Prior to this sitting, I’ve only ever spent time with small sections of this text. For example, sections 75 and 76 in the second part on teleological judgment were major catalysts driving my earliest attempts to counter mechanistic biology by replacing it withย an alternative theory of organism (for example, this essay written between 2008 andย 2009). At that point, I had paid almost no attention to the first part on aesthetic judgment. Having read overย that part twice now in the past few weeks, I realize that I had not fully understood what was at stake in Kant’s attempt to articulate a criticalย philosophy of biology, i.e., a transcendental study of life itself. The key take away for me was Kant’s denial of scientific genius. Only artists, and especially poets, can be considered geniuses. A genius is natureย appearingย in the form of the human being giving the rule to art. A genius is someone who, without following explicit rules and so according to a method mysteriousย even toย themselves, is able toย giveย artistic expression to the formative forces of nature. Without the slightest contrivance, as though they emerged merely from the free play of the imagination, genius is able to produce beautiful works that, for those with cultivated taste at least,ย are suggestive of supersensibleย ideas and cosmicย intelligences.
But the notion of a scientific genius is a contradiction in terms, since for Kant natural science presupposes the lawful system of categories imposed universally upon our experience of nature by the understanding. Science produces conceptually determinant knowledge about nature, principally in the formย of synthetic a priori logical and mathematical constructions (which if they cannot be known a priori are sortedย according toย the sieve of experiment). If a scientist cannot tell you with precision exactly how she came to know what she knows, then she doesn’t know anything. Knowledge production is always such that anyone with sufficient training should be able to grasp it and to reproduce it.ย Artistic genius, however, cannot be taught. Its products remain forever beyond the reach of mere skill or education. Artistic geniuses gain aesthetic insight into nature, but fail to provide any scientificย knowledge of nature. Scientists, according to Kant, can catchย no cognitive sightย (i.e., they have no intellectual intuition)ย ofย the hidden cause of nature’s self-organizing processes.
“It is quite certain,” writes Kant,
“that we can never adequately come to know the organized beings and their internal possibility in accordance with merely mechanical principles of nature, let alone explain them; and indeed this is so certain that we can boldly say that it would be absurd for humans even to make such an attempt or to hope that there may yet arise a Newton who could make comprehensible even the generation of a blade of grass according to natural laws that no intention has ordered; rather, we must absolutely deny this insight to human beings” (section 75).
When it comes to our power to judge whether the apparently teleological or end-seeking aspects of nature (in its products andย as a whole) are real causes or merely illusory intuitions, Kant resolves whatย would otherwiseย remainย an antinomy for reason by denying natural science any knowledge one way or the other. We simply cannot know scientifically, argues Kant, whether nature is truly mechanical or whether higher ends are shaping its products and processes. Science can neither affirm an intelligent cause behind nature, nor deny that, at least for us as human knowers, such a cause may beย necessary to explain the unity of nature. The concept ofย unity, of course, provides the very condition for the possibility of any natural science at all, and so for Kant, although we cannot know whether nature is objectivelyย purposive, we are justified in our subjective assertions ofย such a purposivenessย because ourย cognitive powers of imagination, understanding, and reason cannot find internal harmony without operating as though thisย purposiveness was real.
My own work on etheric imagination is an attempt to push Kant’s transcendental aesthetics a bit further than he was willing into a fully blown ontology of organism. That he was unwillingย (per his devotion toย the Good) to allow aesthetic feeling (the Beautiful) or scientific knowledge (the True) an equal share in critical philosophy’s transcendental foundation follows from his desire to ground the higher faculties of thinking (the Understanding) and feeling (Taste or Judgment) in that of willing (Reason). The moral law derived from his critique of practical reason was Kant’s trump card. He denied knowledge of nature in order to make room for moral freedom.
In my own work, I hope to show that any search for grounds or foundations always begins and endsย inย imagination (which contains its own sort of freedom, though not always moral). Onceย we acknowledge the peripheral centrality of imagination in philosophy (we find ourselves always in the middle of it, especially when we have tried most to escape from it), the search for foundations is transformed from means to end, which is to say philosophy returns to its generative roots in theย groundlessness of Creativity. We become philosophers once again: lovers of wisdom instead of sophists claiming to be wise; carefulย inquirersย rather than foolhardyย instrumentalizers of nature. Attuned to imagination, we become the spiritual soilย forย nature’s creative expression. Genius becomes the norm instead of the exception. Supposedly commonย human beings are returned their birthright. We realize, as Hillman described it, the poetic basis of mind. Genius cannot be taught; it can only be remembered (though exemplars can help provoke our memories). Through genius–through the feeling and expression of nature become conscious in us as beauty–we gain access to goodness and truth.
Stay tuned…
What do you think?