โ€œThe safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.โ€
โ€“Alfred North Whitehead

Review of Timothy E. Eastman’s ‘Untying the Gordian Knot: Process, Reality, and Context’ [DRAFT]

Below is a draft of a review of Tim Eastman’s new book. I’ll be submitting this to a journal for publication soon, but wanted to share it here for those interested in this important contribution to understanding the nature of reality in light of quantum process.

….

TIMOTHY E. EASTMAN, Untying the Gordian Knot: Process, Reality, and Context. Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books, 2020: 344 pages. [Reviewed by: MATTHEW D. SEGALL, Philosophy, Cosmology, and Consciousness Program, California Institute of Integral Studies, 1453 Mission Street, San Francisco, California, 94103, USA. <msegall@ciis.edu>.] 

It was nearly a century ago, in the midst of the quantum and relativistic revolutions in physics, that Whitehead realized scientific progress had reached a turning point: 

โ€œThe old foundations of scientific thought are becoming unintelligible. โ€ฆWhat is the sense of talking about a mechanical explanation when you do not know what you mean by mechanics? If science is not to degenerate into a medley of ad hoc hypotheses, it must become philosophical and must enter upon a thorough criticism of its own foundations.โ€ 

Despite Whiteheadโ€™s warning, the 1920s also saw the rise of a positivist prohibition on speculative metaphysics, handicapping progress into the foundations of post-classical science and producing precisely the fragmented medley that he feared. Fortunately, a growing chorus of interdisciplinary scientists is taking up the philosophical work left unfinished by the early twentieth century founders of quantum theory. In Untying the Gordian Knot (UGK), plasma physicist-cum-philosopher Timothy E. Eastman adds his voice to the ensemble, offering the โ€œLogoi frameworkโ€ as a meta-theory that aims not only to make ontological sense of quantum mechanics, but to integrate it with several other emerging twenty-first century frameworks, including complex systems science, Peircean triadic semiotics, and category theory. This alone would make Eastmanโ€™s book worthy of careful study; but he goes even further, sketching the plan for a bridge between science (or โ€œthe way of numbersโ€) and the human ethical and spiritual spheres (โ€œthe way of contextโ€). Despite the grand scope of his inquiry, Eastman remains humble and conciliatory: the Logoi framework โ€œis not post-anything but a proto-worldviewโ€ (11) that seeks to balance both theory and story, both systematic rigor and open-ended adventure (14). Eastmanโ€™s masterful synthesis of dozens of cutting edge researchers across numerous disciplines is impossible to summarize in this short review. Thus, in what follows, I focus on a few of UGK‘s important contributions to the birth of a process-relational science.

Eastman decided to study physics and philosophy not only because he wanted to understand the physical world, but because from a young age he intuited that this โ€œwondrous wholeโ€ contained layers of meaning deeper than the merely measurable (1). Natural science has allowed human beings to reach beyond the mundane proportions of their sense organs and species-specific umwelt toward extreme magnitudes of space and time. Telescopes extend our eyesight across vast distances of intergalactic space; microscopes into the nuclei of cells and even atoms; inferences from radioactive decay rates of certain isotopes allow us to infer the age of fossils millions or billions of years into the past. Such techniques have dramatically expanded our understanding of the universe, and our place within it. But in extending our senses to scales they were not evolved to perceive, often while using empirical concepts derived from human-scale perception, we run the risk of succumbing to the sort of model-centric literalism that imagines we possess an outside God’s eye-view of an already finished universe. Eastman seeks to re-embed the scientific perspective within the evolving universe that gave rise to it, such that โ€œthe most fundamental notions [of natural science] can be inferred from normal human experienceโ€ (5). This follows from Eastmanโ€™s commitment to the Whiteheadian ideal that โ€œconcrete existence explains the abstract aspects of experience and not vice versaโ€ (as articulated by Randall Auxier and Gary Herstein [2017, 2]).

Eastman carefully deconstructs the conceptual impediments to philosophical integration of post-classical science, such as โ€œactualism,โ€ โ€œnominalism,โ€ and โ€œdeterminismโ€ (89), arguing that potentials (or potentiae in his terms) have a creative role to play that both upsets notions of (efficient) causal closure and reintroduces formal causes into our accounts of natural processes. While quantum physics has forced the issue, Eastman points out that it is misleading to construe even the formalisms of classical Newtonian physics as though they entail strict determinism, since all such modeling frameworks make assumptions about initial and boundary conditions, relevant scales, and domains for meaningful solution (94). Granting potentiae real participation in the physical world not only allows science to consider the anticipatory capacities and creative agency of biological organisms in a non-reductive way. It also resolves longstanding quantum puzzles, which resulted from trying to force-fit a classical mechanistic ontology to results that should indicate the need for a new, process-relational ontology (54). Building on the Relational Reality model of Epperson and Zafiris (2013), Eastman describes the evolution of quantum events from pure potential to probabilities to actualization when measured (a process involving both logical conditioning and causal re-iteration) (38). Integrating Ruth Kastner‘s Transactional Interpretation of quantum mechanics (2013), Eastman argues that acts of measurement are not passive observations of already existing facts, but rather themselves establish new facts. There can be no ultimate causal closure, either for finite systems or for the universe as a whole, since the ontological unrest of newly emerging facts break any such closure. The universe thus becomes a cumulative succession of โ€œactual occasions of experience,โ€ wherein potentiae grow together with actualities by linking local causal interactions with global logical constraints in the ongoing process of realization. This process is asymmetric and includes both a standard (Boolean) dyadic logic of actualizations (res extensae) and a triadic logic of potentialities (res potentiae) (23). Eastman argues that โ€œdyadic relations do not, in fact, exist in the real world, [only in] the world of abstract modelingโ€ (27). This is because context is inevitably involved, and because the relationship between potentiality and actuality is inherently asymmetrical, from whence comes the arrow of time.

Eastmanโ€™s Logoi framework (again, following Epperson and Zafiris) thus carries forward Whiteheadโ€™s crucial distinction in Process & Reality (1978) between the logical order of concrete events (โ€œgenetic divisionโ€) and the causal order of metrical spacetime (โ€œcoordinate divisionโ€) (43-44). The former, rooted in fundamental quantum processes, is given primacy, while the latter, rather than being conceived of as a pre-existing continuum serving as a container for processes, is secondarily emergent from such processes (68). In Eastmanโ€™s words: 

โ€œQuantum physics exemplifies the fact that physical extensiveness (standard spacetime description) is fundamentally topological rather than metrical, with its proper logico-mathematical framework being category-theoretic (relations of relations) rather than set-theoretic (sets of things)โ€ (71).

Grasping the significance of Eastmanโ€™s Logoi framework may be aided by contrasting it with popular actualist accounts. Eastman critiques the physical โ€œtheory of everythingโ€ articulated by Sean Carroll in his book The Big Picture: On the Origins of Life, Meaning, and the Universe Itself (2016). Carroll takes up the Godโ€™s eye perspective by offering a single โ€œcore theory,โ€ an equation combining quantum mechanics, spacetime, gravity, matter, the Higgs field, and other forces, which he claims leaves no room for new aspects of the universe that are not already well understood. Eastman points out that, while the components of this core equation represent great achievements, in practice no one has ever succeeded in combining them into a practical model or simulation. Carrollโ€™s core theory thus amounts to no more than a mashup and is not anywhere close to being a working equation (126). On Eastmanโ€™s reading, Carroll makes several unstated metaphysical assumptions including actualism, physicalism, and causal closure, leading him to mistake an amalgam of dyadic input-output models as though they could serve as an ultimate explanation for the universe (127). Rather than accepting Carrollโ€™s actualist rendering of the Feynman path-integral formulation of quantum physics (where electrons are assumed to take every path, with the largest probability being given to that path which approaches classical physics), Eastman argues that โ€œphysical relations emerge from [the] multiple sampling of potentiae pre-space, which is operationally handled by the principle of least action, reflecting optimization of relations of relations in this pre-spaceโ€ (138). Rather than prematurely limiting our creative cosmos to the idealized deductivist models of current physics, or suggesting untestable โ€œscientific exoticaโ€(82) like the vast ontological overflow of actualized possible worlds as in the โ€œmany-worldsโ€ interpretation, Eastman leaves open the possibility of genuinely novel emergence within the only universe we could ever know anything about. 

Whiteheadโ€™s cosmology, along with Peirceโ€™s and contemporary physicist Lee Smolinโ€™s ideas, are often interpreted as implying that physical โ€œlawโ€ is more a matter of empirical probability, rather than being metaphysically grounded. Since deism is no longer a live option for scientists (as it was in Descartesโ€™ and Newtonโ€™s day), very few have attempted to ground โ€œlawโ€ metaphysically (130). The closest thing contemporary physics has to such a metaphysical ground for physical laws are โ€œsymmetry principles.โ€ But from Eastmanโ€™s perspective, these principles remain groundlessly circular descriptions without an accompanying process-relational ontology. Peirce attempted to reformulate laws as habits, but Eastman worries this may be a category error that, despite Peirceโ€™s realist intentions, falls prey to nominalism. For Eastman, genuine habits can only be said to emerge at the biological level. Without wanting to affirm deductivism, he nonetheless thinks necessity must have some purchase in Nature for many of the findings of modern physics to make any sense. He thus argues that Natureโ€™s laws derive, not from any deductive necessity, but rather from the conditional contingency of trajectory optimizing histories (e.g., the Principle of Least Action) (131).  He compares these trajectories to Leibnizโ€™ โ€œstriving possiblesโ€ (133).

In addition to its paradigm remaking implications for physics, the Logoi frameworkโ€™s fundamental distinction between the Boolean domain of actualized measurements and the non-Boolean domain of pre-space potentiae also has important implications for the study of human consciousness. Rather than reducing our concrete experience of mental processing to abstract correlations among measurable brain states, the Logoi framework allows us to take seriously our sense of being conscious agents capable of some degree of decisive influence over the ongoing flux of reality. With the inclusion of the realm of potentiae into physical ontology, human consciousness need no longer be thought of as an anomalous intruder into an otherwise well-behaved mechanical universe. Instead, our conscious experience offers us an intimate window into the function of potentiae in the broader course of Nature, as our everyday mental capacities involving tapping into and expressing โ€œontologically genuine remainder[s] of real possibilityโ€ (84). It follows that popular claims on behalf of artificial intelligence systems said to be on the verge of realizing effectively human levels of consciousness and cognition are rooted in faulty metaphysical presuppositions. AI systems are entailment devices limited to input-output (Boolean) logic alone, and so cannot tap into the realm of potentiae in the way biologically evolved, historically emergent minds can (98). 

Eastman synthesizes important insights from a variety of researchers to contribute much needed clarity to the scientific understanding the role of emergence in Nature. Emergent physical entities are so described because as novel wholes they are not derivable either from the stuff of which they are made nor from the laws of physics (111). Eastman distinguishes emergence as a synchronic hierarchical process that builds on diachronic causation. Many basic causal and emergent processes are rooted in multi-scale quantum field processes (Eastman gives the example of space plasmas, whose emergent processes range from planetary to galactic scales) (112). Emergence is thus not merely a matter of epistemic limits to reductive explanations, but rather a consequence of the influence of quantum process across all physical scales. In the Logoi framework, causation is interpreted more broadly than just the dyadic correlation of facts typical of actualist frameworks. From within an actualist framework, any novelty or emergence can only be regarded as an epiphenomenon arising from random error or chance. Understanding emergent entities and processes requires symbolic bridges, as knowledge presupposes a distinction between knower and known, and thus the need for mediation (113). Eastman proposes Whiteheadian โ€œprehensionโ€ as one such symbolic-conceptual bridge. Eastman shares Charles Hartshorneโ€™s sense that prehension is the most powerful metaphysical generalization ever accomplished (159n18), as it allows all sorts of relations (e.g., memory, perception, causality, spatial, temporal, subject-object, God-world, etc.) to be accounted for in terms of one generic type. Further, the metaphysics of prehension imply that all physical relations are fundamentally asymmetrical in structure. Prehension can be variously understood as a philosophical embodiment of field theory; as the ontologization of the mathematical function; and as an account of quantum process (113-114). In light of Whiteheadโ€™s prehensional account of causation and emergence and Epperson and Zafirisโ€™ applications (2013), Eastman argues that a strong case can be made for the idea that all macro-systems (including relativistic spacetime) are ontologically emergent from fundamental quantum processes.  

Although Eastman creatively expands upon Whiteheadโ€™s process philosophy, he does so without remaining unduly tied to the latterโ€™s categoreal scheme. He emphasizes Leemon McHenryโ€™s (2017) interpretation of Whiteheadian prehensions as โ€œconcrete functionsโ€ rather than โ€œabstract relationsโ€ (40), thus contrasting Whiteheadโ€™s โ€œthird approachโ€ to his former collaborator Bertrand Russellโ€™s nominalistic logical atomism. Prehension is defined in its physical mode as โ€œthe present occasionโ€™s absorption of past actual occasions in its process of self-creationโ€ (McHenry, 325). This leaves out the role of conceptual prehensions in Whiteheadโ€™s scheme, that is, the present occasionโ€™s ingression of potentials or eternal objects in its process of self-creation. McHenry (2015) appears to question the need for Whiteheadโ€™s eternal objects (at least if they are given a โ€œPlatonic emphasisโ€ (47). Eastman claims his account of a diachronic process in terms of pre-space potentiae plays a role similar to that of Whiteheadโ€™s โ€œprehensive unificationโ€ first introduced in Science and the Modern World (1925). Despite approving of Whiteheadโ€™s perspectival account of the relation between universals and particulars (103), Eastman sometimes indicates a desire to distance himself from Whitehead’s eternal objects, thus implying that there may be important differences between his landscapes of potentiae and the realm of eternal objects. This is a fertile area for further philosophical exploration beyond the scope of this brief review. Nonetheless, a few suggestions can be offered. 

One way of beginning such an exploration stems from asking whether the choice of realism over nominalism as regards the status of form in Nature entails Platonism. Eastman thinks not (92), but given that Plato wrote dialogues and not doctrines, it all depends what is meant by โ€œPlatonism.โ€ Regardless of the nature of his divergence from Whiteheadโ€™s category of eternal objects, they clearly share a rejection of nominalism. Eastman puts forward an argument against nominalist actualism that is rooted in quantum potentiae that integrate local-global interactions without themselves having any specific spacetime location. They are generals, in C. S. Peirceโ€™s sense, serving as logical constraints on physical process. From Eastmanโ€™s point of view, admitting potentiae back into Nature is far more parsimonious than the actualist/nominalist interpretations of quantum theory (e.g., the many-worlds and multiverse hypotheses) (94). 

Eastman concludes his book with an attempt to link human and cosmic logoi in search of some sense of the deeper meaning of our existence. Careful to avoid any monological fixations, he builds on George Ellisโ€™ โ€œKenotic moralityโ€ (2020, 13), wherein human values like truth, goodness, and beauty โ€œreflect the forces or intentions that created the universeโ€ฆas part of the deep structure of the cosmos,โ€ in Ellisโ€™ terms. Eastman also amplifies Robert Nevilleโ€™s (2013, 53) worry about the โ€œenormous damage to human civilization [resulting from] the loss of value-reference and realistic valuation in modern Western scienceโ€ (245). With characteristic caution and modesty, Eastman seeks to contrast his own Logoi framework, which aims at โ€œevidence-based methodology,โ€ with the โ€œadvocacy-based thinkingโ€ that is more appropriate in cultural and political spheres (247). 

In the final pages, Eastman honors the Dakota peoples, upon whose land he first had the spiritual experience that initiated his inquiry into the nature of reality:

โ€œIn confronting the psychological challenges of nihilism, denialism, and assorted despairs of contemporary life, in facing up to the physical threats of war, pandemics, human suffering, and in newly realizing the deteriorating of earth’s climate, ecology, and habitability, can we somehow embrace what we have learned through science and philosophy and what we may yet draw on from indigenous and other spiritualities so as to bring into being a world in which we humans can live and flourish over the long term?โ€ (274).

Eastman has succeeded in making a major contribution toward such an integral embrace.ย 

Works Cited 

Auxier, Randall and Herstein, Gary. (2017). The Quantum of Explanation: Whiteheadโ€™s Radical Empiricism. New York: Routledge.

Carroll, Sean. (2016). The Big Picture: On the Origins of Life, Meaning, and the Universe Itself. New York: Dutton.

Ellis, George  F. R. (2020). โ€œA Mathematical Cosmologist Reflects on Deep Ethics: Reflections on Values, Ethics, and Morality.โ€ Theology and Science: 1-15. 

Epperson, Michael and Zafiris, Elias. (2013). Foundations of Relational Realism: A Topological Approach to Quantum Mechanics and the Philosophy of Nature. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.ย 

Kastner, Ruth. (2013). The Transactional Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: The Reality of Possibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

McHenry, Leemon. (2017). โ€œWhitehead and Russell on the Analysis of Matter.โ€ The Review of Metaphysics 71: 321-342. 

Neville, Robert. (2013). Ultimates: Philosophical Theology, Volume One. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. 

Advertisement

Comments

17 responses to “Review of Timothy E. Eastman’s ‘Untying the Gordian Knot: Process, Reality, and Context’ [DRAFT]”

  1. simonemah Avatar
    simonemah

    Fascinating !!!

    Thank you for bringing this to my attention !!!

    Simone

  2. Herman Greene Avatar
    Herman Greene

    Thanks for this Matt.

    As you may know I was a reviewer of Eastman’s book when it was in draft phase. While neither of us is physicists,you know more about the science than I do. Perhaps I only helped by asking questions that a reader like me would have.

    I am so pleased you are taking leadership in the process community on science, nd even more the leadership you are taking as a relatively young process scholar and educator. You engage thinkers of your generation and beyond in a contemporary dialogue on process philosophy.

    You are a shining light in a new generation of process studies.

    Herman

    1. Matthew David Segall Avatar

      Thanks, Herman! Timโ€™s book was a heavy lift for me! There are parts I am still struggling to fully understand, particularly with regard to category theory. But the framework is so far reaching, it was helpful to be able to grasp its significance across disciplines I am more familiar with (e.g., biology and consciousness studies).

  3. ggoldbergmd Avatar

    The recognition that there is an underlying hidden relational reality of possibility, out of which the physical universe actualizes via a process of the actualization of possibility, is a fundamental and profound insight that is found prominently in the mystical tradition with which I am familiar, the Kabbalah, where one of the terms for the Shekhinah (ie. the channel through which the influence of the G-dhead, Ayin, enters the physical world) brought forward in ‘The Book of Mirrors’ by David ben Yehudah He-Hasid, is ‘Sod HaEfshar’ translated from the Hebrew as ‘The Secret of the Possible.’ And it is also captured quite beautifully, I think, in Ruth E Kastner’s ‘Possibilist/Relativistic’ version of the Transactional Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics ( see: http://transactionalinterpretation.org/ ). But one area where these ideas have great significance, I think, is in the understanding of our current stage and situation in the evolution of human consciousness. That is a topic addressed most eloquently by the work of Jean Gebser, in his book ‘The Ever-Present Origin’ which is very nicely summarized by Fernando Villalovs at:

    https://en.arkesoul.org/post/jean-gebser-and-the-philosophy-of-consciousness

    The insights here, I believe, can be usefully and importantly applied to making the transition from the age of the current structure of consciousness that is winding down rapidly, the ‘Mental/Rational Structure’, to the new age ramping up with emergence of the ‘Integral Structure’ which is becoming a more and more urgent human global agenda. If we are, in fact, on the cusp of an era in which we are witness to a rapid rise in existential risk that our species will undergo extinction, along with many others, due to the transformations currently occurring across the planet with the arrival of the Anthropocene Age, then the need for this fundamental mutation in the structure of human consciousness is of utmost importance…

    1. Matthew David Segall Avatar

      Great connections here. Eastman does not mention Kabbalah in his book, but the resonances are clear enough.
      I agree, also, the increasing recognition of the role of “potentiae” in cosmogenesis in scholars like Eastman, Epperson, Kastner, et al is another indication of the inception of the integral structure of consciousness.

  4. ggoldbergmd Avatar

    It seems to me that Timothy Eastman’s ‘untying of the Gordian Knot’ and Jean Gebser’s transformation, or ‘mutation’ in the structure of human consciousness (I would actually call it a transformation in human META-consciousness, if we accept the tenet of panpsychism, the indigenous cultures and the world’s mystical faith traditions that EVERYTHING is imbued with consciousness in its ‘primary’ form) from the Mental/Rational structure to the Integral structure, can be recognized as inter-related. I have not read Eastman’s book yet but, thanks to your review, am planning to take a close look, so I don’t know exactly where the two perspectives may overlap, but I do know quite a bit about what Gebser has to say about what ‘advances’ must occur for the Integral structure to ‘take hold’, which all have a great deal to do with our perceptions and understanding of time and process–about which folks like Henri Bergson and AN Whitehead and CS Peirce, and yourself, Matthew, have tried to beat the drum. That we are stuck in a Nominalistic nose-dive. Does Eastman deal with this? I am assuming that he must. Gebser talks about the need for a ‘concretion of time’ and the emergence of an aperspectival worldview from the current limitations of the perspectival view dominated by our conquering of the territories of the external space of the Earth’s atmosphere, ‘outer’ space, and the underwater space of the oceans, while being ‘time-bound’ to the linear spatialized time ‘of the physicist’ in which the present moment divides the past from the future, and having a science which is really a physical ‘scientism’ which gives us, as was pointed out by Walker Percy in his essay and Jefferson Lecture titled ‘The Fateful Rift’ ( see: https://manwithoutqualities.com/2014/04/23/the-san-andreas-fault-in-the-modern-mind/ ), a totally incoherent view of our own nature founded on a non-relational, nominalistic materialism that has completely f’ed us over…

    1. Matthew David Segall Avatar

      He does spend a good number of pages taking nominalist actualism to task, and fleshing out other possibilities (namely the possibility that possibilities themselves are real features of reality!)

  5. ggoldbergmd Avatar

    Also really like your paper on time for the Einstein vs Bergson book. Here is my take on that debate:
    Einstein apparently shuts Bergson down but standing up and making an emphatic pronouncement (apparently in German-accented French) that ‘The time of the philosopher does not exist!’ Which is essentially true. But Bergson so mised out on generating a come-back to Einstein that could have completely shut him down: “So, Herr Einstein, it may be true that the time of the philosopher does not exist, but the time of the physicist is not real!’ This would have been a real doozie, I think, because Einstein would not have had much recourse. As a Nominalist–at least at that point in his life–he would have believed that what was existent was obviously also ‘real’. But would he have been prepared to question that basic assumption? In fact, a Realist who recognized the fundamental significance of relation in determining the nature of reality would have understood the distinction between Chronos, Einstein’s ‘time of the physicist’, and Kairos, Bergson’s ‘time of the philosopher’, and recognized that the truth of the matter is that while Chronos ‘exists’ as part of physical ‘actuality’–basically as linear spatialized quantitative counting of the ‘ticks’ of a physical oscillator–it is NOT real. Because it is external, physical and actual, it is, in Einstein’s own conceptualization of ‘Special Relativity’ dependent on physical context–in particular, relative velocity between inertial frames with respect to the speed of light, c, as the upper limit ‘reference point’.
    So what then is real? What is ultimately real is concrete experience, not measurement of external abstractions. That is where the Nominalist goes off the rails, so to speak. By assuming that what thought produces as an abstraction–namely, things and events in a space-time ‘container’–is ‘real’, the Nominalist mistakes the abstract for the concrete, the map for the territory. And we have gone off the rails for some time now and it may have given us a good deal of insight about how things work in the realm of physical actuality, it has led us far astray from the reality of subjective experience and the reality of the ‘phenomena’ themselves–Peirce called in ‘phaneroscopy.’ Which is the recognition of the primacy of the concrete domain of experience–wherein our reality truly lies. But what is the nature of that reality? Well, that is where quantum physics, potentially, comes to the rescue. Reality entails ‘the reality of possibility’ as Ruth Kastner calls it, which is fundamentally relational. That is the ‘hidden’ reality that our physical senses do not directly register. Nominalism tells us that there is no such thing as a true ‘general’ or ‘universal’ essence. That the only ‘truth’ comes from the registration of the physical ‘instantiations’. And that the relations are mind-dependent inferences that we draw from the behavior of the physically detectable ‘relata’. But what if it ‘really’ is the other way around? that what is ‘true’ are the universals? And how they determine possibility for actualization in the context of ‘QuantumLand’? Well that would really change everything, wouldn’t it? What if our only direct access to concrete reality is in the present moment of the Now (as Rupert Spira calls it)? And if everything that we ‘think’ is real is actually constructed by thought from the brief ‘glimpse’ of eternity that we get in the Now? What if we have evolved a NON-VERIDICAL interface (as Donald Hoffman maintains in his work with the Essentia Foundation and in his book ‘The Case Against Reality’) with physicality that actually HIDES REALITY FROM US? That this hidden reality is ‘the reality of possibility’ which is the realm of QuantumLand? Then what? Then who wins the debate?

    1. ggoldbergmd Avatar

      By the way, this whole thing is also the central issue in Iain McGilchrist’s wonderful new two-volume book titled ‘The Matter with Things. Our Brains, Our Delusions, and the Unmaking of the World.’ We have let the ‘Emissary’ take over the role of the ‘Master’ which it was never really designed to handle, and so we are sliding down the slippery slope of a Nominalistic ‘hell’ where skeptical nihilism is an end result, moral depravity is widespread because there are no moral foundations for taking responsibility for one’s own behavior and for the welfare of the Other, and the actual basis for the process of inquiry and discovery is fundamentally undermined. Peirce warned us over 100 years ago that we were sliding into a Nominalistic wasteland–he called it Necessitarianism… a world deprived of Thirdness, of ‘mediation’ and functioning without the benefit of ‘Evolutionary Love’ as a guiding principle.
      Nathan Houser highlights these problems with the Nominalistic worldview that dominates throughout Western modern culture in his discussion and review of Paul Forster’s book called ‘Peirce and the Threat of Nominalism’ which appeared a few years ago in the Notre Dame Philosophical Review… https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/peirce-and-the-threat-of-nominalism/
      The late John Deely was also very concerned and noted that we are in a time of transition between an ‘Age of Ideas’ to which the Cartesian foray into Nominalism and Dualism directed modernity (it was actually a political solution that gave the body to the Natural Philosophers and the soul to the Men of the Church), and a new ‘Age of Signs’ which will fully recognize the primacy of relationality and the reality of communication. Deely was way out ahead on all of this, I would say… (and have probably pointed this out here before to anyone who would listen!) … in his great work titled ‘The Four Ages of Understanding’ and in an important paper titled ‘Toward a Postmodern Recovery of ‘Person”….

      See: https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.3138/9781442675032/html?lang=en

      ….and see: https://www.revistaespiritu.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/12/Dialnet-TowardAPostmodernRecoveryOfPerson-4102375.pdf

      So much more that can be said about all of this and its fundamental implications for our current situation… but wanted to point out that I will be presenting on a related topic for the Pari Center for New Learning on February 19th…

      https://paricenter.com/event/connecting-the-actuality-of-things-in-space-time-to-the-reality-of-possibility-in-quantumland/

      1. ggoldbergmd Avatar

        That Pari Center presentation is being done together with Ruth E Kastner… see: http://transactionalinterpretation.org/

      2. Matthew David Segall Avatar

        Thanks for this lovely thoughts. BTW, John Deely is cited frequently in Eastman’s book.

      3. Gary Goldberg Avatar
        Gary Goldberg

        Yes, I have managed to do an initial read of the book now and there is much to commend about it including the frequent citing of John Deely in bringing semiotics as the science of relationality into the picture, with the recognition that the human is the quintessential ‘Semiotic Animal’–the creature that not only utilizes ‘semiosis’ (ie. a process of signification) but can reflect upon the fact and describe the process of signification in exposition–knowing what a sign is and how it is utilized, which adds an additional level of reflection given that ‘Semiotics’ is the examination of knowing how we know. So that this study–ie. the work of ‘Semiotics’– could be construed as the knowledge related to the knowing of how we know.

      4. Matthew David Segall Avatar

        Thank you for sharing news of your talk at the Pari center! I will see if I can track down the recording as I will be teaching at that time.

  6. philiptryon Avatar
    philiptryon

    Hi Matt,A few quick things:It turns out I will be able to be there Saturday and can watch for myself for any discussions about embodiment of recurring processes or the relationship of inclination to causation in terms of influencing the outcomes of events. I read your review and found it difficult to digest. There are a lot of complex words strung together in sentences that are not easy for me to to parse, especially on first reading. I think you need to simplify it a bit.It also seems to me that you highlighted some of the weaknesses of this book in the details you chose to include. See attached.Phil

    1. Matthew David Segall Avatar

      Glad you’ll be able to make it, Philip! I am sorry you found this review difficult. I’ll keep working to unpack some of those dense sentences while still remaining in the word limit of a book review. As for inclinations/influences and causality, I happened to see this article on Ruth Kastner’s blog linked above. Might be relevant to your questions? https://transactionalinterpretation.org/2021/05/08/why-arguments-against-free-will-based-on-physics-are-hugely-overrated/

  7. Tim Eastman Unties the Gordian Knot: Complete Seminar (Sessions 1-9) – Footnotes2Plato Avatar

    […] with the author and the interested public. I’ve recently reviewed Eastman’s book HERE. Those interested in the implications of a rigorous process philosophical interpretation of quantum […]

What do you think?

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

%d bloggers like this: